A terribly serious adventure Philosophy and war at Oxford, 1900-1960

Nikhil Krishnan

Book - 2023

"What are the limits of language? How can philosophy be brought closer to everyday life? What is a good human being? These were among the questions that philosophers wrestled with in mid-twentieth-century Britain, a period shadowed by war and the rise of fascism. In response to these events, thinkers such as Philippa Foot (originator of the famous trolley problem), Isaiah Berlin, Iris Murdoch, Elizabeth Anscombe, Gilbert Ryle, and J. L. Austin aspired to a new level of watchfulness and self-awareness about language as a way of keeping philosophy true to everyday experience. A Terribly Serious Adventure traces the friendships and the rivalries, the shared preoccupations and the passionate disagreements of some of Oxford's most inno...vative thinkers. Far from being stuck in their ivory towers, the Oxford philosophers lived. They were codebreakers, diplomats, and soldiers in both World Wars, and they often drew on their real-world experience in creating their greatest works, masterpieces of British modernism original in both thought and style"--

Saved in:

2nd Floor Show me where

190.904/Krishnan
1 / 1 copies available
Location Call Number   Status
2nd Floor 190.904/Krishnan Checked In
Subjects
Genres
Biographies
History
Published
New York : Random House [2023]
Language
English
Main Author
Nikhil Krishnan (author)
Edition
First American edition
Physical Description
xxiv, 368 pages ; 25 cm
Bibliography
Includes bibliographical references (pages 299-321) and index.
ISBN
9780525510604
  • Giddiness
  • Fog
  • Nonsense
  • Argy-bargy
  • Blood
  • Saturdays
  • Corruption
  • Swimming
  • Thaw
  • Donkeys
  • Ghosts.
Review by Publisher's Weekly Review

Krishnan, a professor of moral philosophy at the University of Cambridge, debuts with an ambitious but underwhelming study of "Oxford philosophy," an intellectual tradition defined by such virtues as humility, self awareness, and directness. Aiming to convey "not just what people thought but they were like," Krishnan profiles a large cast of characters who studied and taught at Oxford between the world wars, including novelist and moral philosopher Iris Murdoch, whose forays into French existentialism led her to publish the "first comprehensive work in English" on Sartre, and J.L. Austin, a proponent of "ordinary language philosophy," who sought "to 'dissolve' philosophical problems by showing them to emerge out of misunderstandings of language." Though the premise fascinates, Krishnan struggles to weave the philosophers' narratives together, resulting in a history that sometimes feels like a hodgepodge of amusing anecdotes rather than a unified whole. Links between the philosophers' personal lives and the development of Oxford philosophy are also occasionally unclear--for instance, Krishnan notes that there were "sectarians of at least three different stripes" at Oxford when Gilbert Ryle arrived but doesn't fully explain how they might have affected Ryle's development as a philosopher, or the evolution of Oxford philosophy as a whole. Despite some bright moments, this never quite comes together. (July)

(c) Copyright PWxyz, LLC. All rights reserved
Review by Kirkus Book Review

Parsing the language of philosophy. In his debut book, Krishnan, who holds a doctorate in philosophy from Oxford, brings wry wit and adroit observations to his investigation of the rise of analytic, or linguistic, philosophy at his alma mater. A department staffed by idealists, realists, and one pragmatist--F.C.S. Schiller--was shaken up by influences from near (Cambridge) and far (Vienna), and questions of meaning and language rose to new importance. "The special business of philosophy," Krishnan writes, "was to scrape away at sentences until the content of the thoughts underlying them was revealed, their form unobstructed by the distorting structures of language and idiom." Analytic philosophy, its adherents believed, would foster "particular virtues" that Oxfordians held dear: humility, self-awareness, collegiality, restraint, elegance, concision, and directness. Krishnan chronicles the transformation, and the energetic debates it inspired, by focusing on salient figures, beginning with the "pipe-chewing, no nonsense" Gilbert Ryle, who, while at Oxford, became acquainted with G.E. Moore and Wittgenstein at Cambridge and discovered Husserl and Heidegger. His classmate A.J. Ayer, "whose greatest non-philosophical interest was women," also studied in Vienna, where he encountered the American logician Willard Van Orman Quine and philosopher Ernest Nagel. Émigrés such as Isaiah Berlin, Ernst Cassirer, and Theodor Adorno brought ideas from Europe directly to Oxford. By the late 1930s, there were women involved, as well: Mary Scrutton, on scholarship; the fiery Elizabeth Anscombe, who pressed her colleagues to consider ethical consequences of their positions; the quietly sensible Philippa Foot; and the defiantly bohemian Iris Murdoch, who introduced British readers to Sartre. Beginning in the late 1950s, the likes of social critic Herbert Marcuse and New Left Review editor Perry Anderson critiqued the Oxfordians for being insular. Nevertheless, for four decades, they had carried out a formidable task: "to explain what we mean by what we ordinarily say." A lively, well-researched intellectual history. Copyright (c) Kirkus Reviews, used with permission.

Copyright (c) Kirkus Reviews, used with permission.

1 Fog Gilbert Ryle (b.1900), the first-born of the protagonists of this story, grew up in Sussex, sunniest of English counties. In later life, he told a sort of origin story for himself. A bright young schoolmaster at young Ryle's school, just "down from Oxford," asked his class the kind of question Socrates would have relished: "What is color?" "Paint," replied one unassuming lad. Ryle smirked knowingly. Asked if he could do better, he said something to the effect that a color is the power of an object to produce a certain kind of sensation in us. It was what, a few years later, he knew to call "a Lockean sort of answer." "I scored five marks for my sapience," the grown-up know-it-all recalled in his memoir. Ryle belonged to a generation of men who had just started to call each other by their Christian names, but he was inconsistent on the matter. We had better play it safe and call him "Ryle." His grandfather was the first bishop of Liverpool, and the author of a steady stream of readable theological treatises with titles like Knots Untied. Old Bishop Ryle sought salvation in the Word of God, "the Word made clear to the head and applied to the heart." Woolliness was the chief instrument of the devil, his way of dividing Christian from Christian; God's work called for his servants to do better. "If men would only define with precision the theological terms which they use, many disputes would die. Scores of excited disputants would discover . . . that their disputes have arisen from their own neglect of the great duty of explaining the meaning of words." He managed to raise an agnostic son--Gilbert's father--who became a prosperous general practitioner with a sideline in philosophical speculation; he was one of the early members of the Aristotelian Society. His own ten children, clever and variously gifted, never had a faith to lose. Gilbert Ryle repudiated the evangelical inheritance but imbibed the family manner and always wrote in the punchy style of his grandfather. He was born in the late summer of 1900, a lucky year to be born an English boy. Just a year older and there was every chance that he would have been one of the 149 boys from Brighton College who died at Ypres, in the Somme or in Palestine, and whose deaths were announced at school assembly. As it was, Ryle survived, eighteen years old at the Armistice, and ready to head for--or "go up to"--Oxford, armed with the confidence of a happy childhood spent under a Brighton sun. His Oxford college was Queen's, on the High Street, dubbed by Pevsner "the grandest piece of classical architecture in Oxford," a product of "the short phase which one has a right to name English Baroque, i.e. Baroque with English reservations." A surviving photograph of Ryle in his twenties could be that of an officer on leave, or a young schoolmaster capable of going from joshing to sternness in a blink. His jaw is set, his eyes hardened; the high forehead portends the baldness of middle age. The one decorative touch is the wet gloss of the Macassar oil holding his immaculate side parting in place. The degree for which he was "reading" was Literae Humaniores, with its two phases, "Moderations" and "Greats." Mods--Oxford leaves nothing serious without a nickname--ended with a grueling set of exams, two a day on average, in Greek and Latin language and literature. It has been said that only the ten-day ordeal that is the Chinese civil service entrance exam is harder. Ryle was halfhearted for those first five terms, a succession of eight intense weeks punctuated with long vacations. He achieved distinction as a rower, rising, as he later put it, "to the giddy height of Captain of Boats." But he found also that he "lacked the ear, the nostrils, the palate, and the toe" of the real classical scholar. It didn't stop him getting a first-class degree anyway, in the only way one is supposed to get a first at Oxford: without trying. Ryle's one early classical love was Aristophanes, whose bawdy plays spared no one but were especially rude about philosophers. (Socrates in The Clouds is mostly interested in examining the rear end of a gnat.) His other early love was logic, "a grown-up subject, in which there were still unsolved problems." "Unsolved" meant, among other things, that the only advantage the old had over the young was that of having had longer to think about the questions. Greats was a peculiar and somewhat unsystematic coupling of history (ancient Greek and Roman) with philosophy (ancient and modern). Ryle "did think that the Academy mattered more than the Peloponnesian War"--the Academy in question being Plato's original--but was left cold by his tutors' attitude to the Republic. They treated it, he recalled, "like the Bible, and to me most of it seemed, philosophically, no better." His tutor at Queen's was Herbert James "Hamish" Paton (b.1887), a Glaswegian in his early thirties who had arrived in Oxford on a seventeenth-century scholarship that had once been held by Adam Smith. Paton had a keen but, as Ryle remembered it, "unfanatical" interest in the philosophy of an Italian contemporary, Benedetto Croce (b.1866), himself an unfanatical follower of Hegel (b.1770). Hegel's cult in Germany had tended--or so it certainly seemed in England--to fanaticism of one kind or another. But Croce, by then the author of a sprightly little book called What Is Living and What Is Dead of the Philosophy of Hegel, preferred the Hegel who decried the more mystical sort of philosophy, "with its frenzies, its sighing, its raising the eyes to heaven, its bowing the neck and clasping the hands, its faintings, its prophetic accents, its mysterious phrases of the initiates." No, said Hegel-as-presented-by-Croce, "philosophy should have a rational and intelligible form." It should be "exoteric," that is to say open to public interpretation, "not a thing of sects, but of humanity." When Ryle started at Oxford, Paton was just returning from Versailles, where he had attended the Paris Peace Conference as an expert on Polish matters. He had picked up his expertise as a member of the intelligence division of the Admiralty, where he, like a few other lucky dons of the decade who managed never to see the inside of a trench, had spent his war years. His students often found him "unforthcoming," but that could mean simply that he refused to give them the answers. Not giving students the answers was at the heart of the distinctive style of teaching Ryle would have encountered at Oxford. From being one of a few dozen boys at Brighton College, he found himself alone in a study with Paton--or occasionally, with one other student--with his opinions being given the closest attention by someone vastly better informed on the subject. There have always been many ways of running an Oxford tutorial, but Paton's model for the task was that of the courtroom cross-examiner. Ryle was among the few to find provocation and excitement in his almost-catchphrase, "Now, Ryle, what exactly do you mean by . . . ?" Excerpted from A Terribly Serious Adventure: Philosophy and War at Oxford, 1900-1960 by Nikhil Krishnan All rights reserved by the original copyright owners. Excerpts are provided for display purposes only and may not be reproduced, reprinted or distributed without the written permission of the publisher.