Tragedy, the Greeks, and us

Simon Critchley, 1960-

Book - 2019

"From the curator of The New York Times's "The Stone," a provocative and timely exploration into tragedy--how it articulates conflicts and contradiction that we need to address in order to better understand the world we live in. We might think we are through with the past, but the past isn't through with us. Tragedy permits us to come face to face with what we do not know about ourselves but that which makes those selves who we are. Having Been Born is a compelling examination of ancient Greek origins in the development and history of tragedy--a story that represents what we thought we knew about the poets, dramatists, and philosophers of ancient Greece--and shows them to us in an unfamiliar, unexpected, and origina...l light"--

Saved in:

2nd Floor Show me where

809.9162/Critchley
1 / 1 copies available
Location Call Number   Status
2nd Floor 809.9162/Critchley Checked In
Subjects
Published
New York : Pantheon Books [2019]
Language
English
Main Author
Simon Critchley, 1960- (author)
Edition
First edition
Physical Description
x, 322 pages ; 22 cm
Bibliography
Includes bibliographical references (pages 287-305) and index.
ISBN
9781524747947
  • Part I. Introduction
  • 1. Feeding the Ancients with Our Own Blood
  • 2. Philosophy's Tragedy and the Dangerous Perhaps
  • 3. Knowing and Not Knowing: How Oedipus Brings Down Fate
  • 4. Rage, Grief, and War
  • 5. Gorgias: Tragedy Is a Deception That Leaves the Deceived Wiser Than the Nondeceived
  • 6. Justice as Conflict (for Polytheism)
  • 7. Tragedy as a Dialectical Mode of Experience
  • Part II. Tragedy
  • 8. Tragedy as Invention, or the Invention of Tragedy: Twelve Theses
  • 9. A Critique of the Exotic Greeks
  • 10. Discussion of Vernant and Vidal-Naquet's Myth and Tragedy in Ancient Greece
  • 11. Moral Ambiguity in Aeschylus's Seven Against Thebes and The Suppliant Maidens
  • 12. Tragedy, Travesty, and Queerness
  • 13. Polyphony
  • 14. The Gods! Tragedy and the Limitation of the Claims to Autonomy and Self-Sufficiency
  • 15. A Critique of Moral Psychology and the Project of Psychical Integration
  • 16. The Problem with Generalizing about the Tragic
  • 17. Good Hegel, Bad Hegel
  • 18. From Philosophy Back to Theater
  • Part III. Sophistry
  • 19. Against a Certain Style of Philosophy
  • 20. An Introduction to the Sophists
  • 11. Gorgiasm
  • 22. The Not-Being
  • 23. I Have Nothing to Say and I Am Saying It
  • 24. Helen Is Innocent
  • 25. Tragedy and Sophistry-The Case of Euripides' The Trojan Women
  • 26. Rationality-'and Force
  • 27. Plato's Sophist
  • 28. Phaedrus, a Philosophical Success
  • 29. Gorgias, a Philosophical Failure
  • Part IV. Plato
  • 30. Indirection
  • 31. A City in Speech
  • 32. Being Dead Is Not a Terrible Thing
  • 33. The Moral Economy of Mimesis
  • 34. Political Forms and Demonic Excess
  • 35. What Is Mimesis?
  • 36. Philosophy as Affect Regulation
  • 37. The Inoculation against Our Inborn Love of Poetry
  • 38. The Rewards of Virtue, or What Happens When We Die
  • Part V. Aristotle
  • 39. What Is Catharsis in Aristotle?
  • 40. More Devastating
  • 41. Reenactment
  • 42. Mimesis Apraxeos
  • 43. The Birth of Tragedy (and Comedy)
  • 44. Happiness and Unhappiness Consist in Action
  • 45. Single or Double?
  • 46. Most Tragic Euripides
  • 47. Monstrosity-Or Aristotle and His Highlighter Pen
  • 48. The Anomaly of Slaves and Women
  • 49. Mechanical Prebuttal
  • 50. The God Finds a Way to Bring About What We Do Not Imagine
  • 51. Misrecognition in Euripides
  • 52. Smeared Makeup
  • 53. Sophocles' Theater of Discomfort
  • 54. Vulgar Acting and Epic Inferiority
  • 55. Is Aristotle Really More Generous to Tragedy Than Plato?
  • 56. Poetics II-Aristotle on Comedy
  • 57. Tormented Incomprehensibly-Against Homeopathic Catharsis
  • 58. Aristophanes Falls Asleep
  • 59. Make Athens Great Again
  • Part VI. Conclusion
  • 60. Transgenerational Curse
  • 61. Aliveness
  • Acknowledgments: Why This Book Was Hard to Write-and Thanks
  • Notes
  • Bibliography
  • Index
Review by Booklist Review

What poet Anne Carson sees in a Detroit foundry a flaming molten core Critchley finds in ancient Greek tragedy. Such tragedy, Critchley argues, delivers life at its fieriest, enveloping audiences in heart-melting grief as it consumes philosophical clarity and moral certainty. Those who view this drama must confront the profound difficulty of choosing a path of action when surrounded by ambiguity. No wonder that Plato feared the civic effects of tragic poetry and therefore banned it from his utopian Republic. But Critchley detects in Plato's political-metaphysical reasoning and in other philosophizing about tragedy a futile attempt to deny contradictions integral to our humanity. In Nietzsche's striking willingness to embrace those contradictions, Critchley finds a perspective on tragedy open to its revelatory and transformative power. Readers feel that power as they probe the dazzling words and tempestuous emotions in the tragedies of Aeschylus, Sophocles, and above all Euripides. Plays such as Seven against Thebes, Oedipus, and Electra leave Critchley and his readers shaken by anguish born of violence and generating it anew. But those who are so shaken, Critchley hopes, can perhaps check our twenty-first-century rush toward a rosy future built of nothing but illusory ideologies and seductive technogadgets. Postmodern philosophy collides with ancient drama, generating the heat of passion, the sparks of illumination.--Bryce Christensen Copyright 2019 Booklist

From Booklist, Copyright (c) American Library Association. Used with permission.
Review by Publisher's Weekly Review

New School philosophy professor Critchley (What We Think About When We Think About Soccer) takes on ancient Greek tragedy's philosophical implications in this dense, demanding study. A self-described "non-classicist," Critchley finds in the classical form a bracing alternative to his own discipline. If philosophy is rational and sensible, then tragedy plays are ambiguous, "giving voice to what is contradictory about us... and what is limited about us." Informing readers unfamiliar with classical literature that in ancient Greek plays "tragedy requires some degree of complicity on our part," he points to the "highest exemplar of tragedy," Sophocles' Oedipus the King, in which the protagonist, seeking to defy a prophecy that he will commit patricide and incest, unknowingly commits both. In this way, the play shows how "we both know and don't know at one and the same time," and how free will allows people to follow a preordained fate. These aren't easy ideas, and this book is not one to be read casually. In his acknowledgments, Critchley writes of initially exploring his ideas in lectures and conversations, an exploratory process evident throughout this intelligent, rigorous book. Dedicated readers will have the sense of being at a thoughtful scholar's side as he works through an intractable intellectual problem. (Apr.) © Copyright PWxyz, LLC. All rights reserved.

(c) Copyright PWxyz, LLC. All rights reserved
Review by Library Journal Review

Critchely (philosophy, New Sch. for Social Research, NY), a specialist in continental philosophy and author of works spanning ethics, Martin Heidegger, and suicide, to David Bowie and soccer, has long studied Greek tragedy and its relationship to philosophy and literature, an obsession coming to a head in a seminar conducted at the New School with philosopher Judith Butler. Here, playing on ideas from thinkers such as Friedrich Nietzsche, Bernard Williams, Peter Szondi, Barbara Cassin, among others, Critchley argues that Greek tragedy represents a philosophical discourse that stimulates thought by embracing ambiguity and resisting the claims of universality or certainty. As such, it is contrary to the rationalist aspirations of Plato and those philosophers who followed. In this, Critchley offers important insights into the sophists, especially Gorgias, as well as a reading of Plato's Republic as a drama antithetical to tragedy. He also presents rich readings on Aristotle, specifically about catharsis, action, and the meaning of comedy. VERDICT Combining a thorough knowledge of Attic drama, fluency with the scholarly literature, and an engaging wit, Critchley's treatment is sophisticated yet accessible to thoughtful general readers. [See Prepub Alert, 10/22/18.]-Thomas L. Cooksey, formerly with Armstrong Atlantic State Univ., Savannah © Copyright 2019. Library Journals LLC, a wholly owned subsidiary of Media Source, Inc. No redistribution permitted.

(c) Copyright Library Journals LLC, a wholly owned subsidiary of Media Source, Inc. No redistribution permitted.
Review by Kirkus Book Review

A philosopher examines ancient drama for insights into morality, power, and freedom.In an erudite reconsideration of Greek tragedy, philosopher Critchley (Philosophy/New School for Social Research; What We Think About When We Think About Soccer, 2017, etc.) asserts that the ancient Greek past offers "a way of questioning and destabilizing the present." Each generation, he writes, has the responsibility of reinventing classical works in order to rescue whatever "will speak to the present and arrest us momentarily from the irresistible pull of the future." In 61 brief chapters, each an inquiry, commentary, or meditation, Critchley offers close readings that assume readers' familiarity with many of the 31 extant tragedies by Euripides, Sophocles, and Aeschylus; iconic playwrights such as Shakespeare, Beckett, and Brecht; philosophical writings of Plato and Aristotle; and critical works on tragedy by philosophers, theorists, and literary scholars from German idealists and romantics to contemporary writers such as Judith Butler, Terry Eagleton, and Anne Carson. Tragedy, Critchley writes, "poses a most serious threat to that invention we call philosophy" because it presents a "conflictually constituted world defined by ambiguity, duplicity, uncertainty, and unknowability." In tragedy, humans must respond "to demands that exceed autonomy, that flow from the past, disrupt the present, and disable the future." Gods stand as "the placeholder for a force or forces that exceed yet determine and can indeed destroy human agency. The gods are names for powers not under our control." Among many unresolved questions about the impact of tragedy on viewers, the author asks about "the inversion of gender roles" in plays centered on the actions of intelligent, courageous women. In rigidly patriarchal Greek society, young men played these roles, and it is not known if women were among audience members. Male viewers, then, were confronted with displays of women's power as well as overwhelming grief. Were such plays "lifelike," Critchley wonders, "or is something more subversive, troubling, and insurrectionary taking place in drama?"For students of Greek drama, a revelatory contemplation of the theater's enduring power. Copyright Kirkus Reviews, used with permission.

Copyright (c) Kirkus Reviews, used with permission.

Introduction   1   Feeding the Ancients with Our Own Blood     Tragedy shows what is perishable, what is fragile, and what is slow moving about us. In a world defined by relentless speed and the unending acceleration of information flows that cultivate amnesia and an endless thirst for the short-term future allegedly guaran­teed through worship of the new prosthetic gods of technology, tragedy is a way of applying the emergency brake.   Tragedy slows things down by confronting us with what we do not know about ourselves: an unknown force that unleashes violent effects on us on a daily, indeed often minute-by-minute basis. Such is the sometimes terrifying presence of the past that we might seek to disavow but that will have its victory in the end, if only in the form of our mortality. We might think we are through with the past, but the past isn't through with us. Through its sud­den reversals of fortune and rageful recognition of the truth of our origins, tragedy permits us to come face-to-face with what we do not know about ourselves but what makes those selves the things they are. Tragedy provokes what snags in our being, the snares and booby traps of the past that we blindly trip over in our relentless, stumbling, forward movement. This is what the ancients called "fate," and it requires our complicity in order to come down on us.   Yet, the fruit of a consideration of tragedy is not a sense of life's hopelessness or moral resignation, as Schopenhauer thought, but--I think--a deepened sense of the self in its utter depen­dency on others. It is a question of the self's vulnerable exposure to apparently familiar and familial patterns of kinship (although it sometimes turns out that, like Oedipus, you don't know who your parents are, but if you do know who your parents are, you still don't know who they are). One of the most salient but enig­matic features of Greek tragedy is its constant negotiation with the other, especially the enemy other, the foreign other, the "barbaric" other. The oldest extant piece of theater that we possess, Aeschy­lus's The Persians, from 472 BCE, depicts the defeated enemy not with triumph but with sympathy and with an anticipation of the possible humiliation that might face the Athenians should they repeat the hybris of the Persians by invading Greece and desecrat­ing the altars of the enemy's gods. Sadly, the Athenians did not heed Aeschylus's lesson, and the brief period of Athenian imperial hegemony in the central decades of the fifth century BCE ended in the humiliating defeat of the Peloponnesian Wars. There is per­haps a moral to be drawn here for our time and place, where the empire knows its heyday is over and we live in a constant state of war. The first rule of war is sympathy with the enemy. This is something that can be seen in the tragedies of Euripides, espe­cially those that deal with the bloody end of the Trojan War, in plays like The Trojan Women and Hecuba.   As Aristotle put it perspicuously and somewhat blithely nearly a century after the zenith of Greek drama in the second half of the fifth century BCE, tragedy is the imitation of action, mimesis praxeos . But what exactly is meant by action? It is far from clear. In play after play of the three great tragedians (Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides), what we see are characters who are utterly disori­ented by the situation in which they find themselves. They do not know how to act. We find human beings somehow compelled to follow a path of suffering that allows them to raise questions that admit of no easy answer: What will happen to me? How can I choose the right path of action? The overwhelming experience of tragedy is a disorientation expressed in one bewildered and fre­quently repeated question: What shall I do?   Tragedy is not about the metaphysical cultivation of the bios theoretikos, the contemplative life that is the supposed fruit of philosophy in Aristotle's Ethics , or in Epicurus and the other Hel­lenistic schools . Nor is it about the cultivation of the life of the gods or divine life, ho bios theois, which is also the constant prom­ise of philosophy from Plato onward, as we will see. No, tragedy is thinking in action, thinking upon action, for the sake of action, where the action takes place offstage and is often described to us indirectly through the character of a messenger. But this thinking takes the form of a radical questioning: How do I act? What shall I do? If tragedy is mimesis praxeos, then it is action that is called into question through tragedy, divided and sliced open. What the experience of tragedy invites is neither the blind impulsiveness of action, nor some retreat into a solitary life of contemplation, but the difficulty and uncertainty of action in a world defined by ambi­guity, where right always seems to be on both sides. Hegel is right to insist that tragedy is the collision between opposed yet mutu­ally justified claims to what is right. But if both sides are right, then what on earth do we do?   Part of the joy of wandering into the ancient world and dealing with seemingly remote phenomena like Attic tragedy (and I will use the adjectives Attic, Athenian, and Greek interchangeably to name the same phenomenon) is how little we know and how little we will ever know. Of the many things we don't know about ancient tragedy, the most important and most enigmatic is some sense of what the spectator was expected to take away from these spectacles. The ancient Greek word for "spectator" was theoros, from which we get the word theoria, theory. Theoria is linked to the verb "to see," theorein, which takes place in a theater, a theatron, to name the act of spectating. If tragedy is the imitation of action, of praxis, although the nature of action remains deeply enigmatic, then praxis is something seen from a theoretical perspective. Or, better said perhaps, the question of theory and practice, or the gap between theory and practice, first opens in theater and as theater. Theater is always theoretical, and theory is a theater, where we are spectators on a drama that unfolds: our drama. In theater, human action, human praxis, is called into question theoretically. Other­wise said, praxis is internally divided or questioned by theoria in the space of the theater, where the empty space of the theater is a way of calling into question the spaces we inhabit and subverting the divisions that constitute social and political space.   Now, aside from a fragment by the great Sophist Gorgias that we will look at in a little while--and Gorgias is one of the heroes of this book--and Aristophanes' The Frogs, where he stages a debate between Euripides and Aeschylus as to who is the best tra­gedian that I will discuss in Part 5, the only spectator reports on tragedy that we possess come from Plato and Aristotle, who had various axes to grind. In the case of Plato, it is a little like basing your view of the Vikings on the reports of the Christian monks whose monasteries they ransacked. Aristotle appears more benev­olent, but appearances can be deceptive. Despite some wonderful and important historical, philological, and archeological work, we have little idea how tragedy was seen and what the audience thought . We have no online reviews, no blogs, and no tweets. Nor do we even know for sure who attended the plays. For example, we cannot be certain whether any women attended the festivals where the tragedies were performed with such an abundance of female characters. But, in my view, far from being a vice, this epis­temic deficit, this lack of knowledge is, I think, a virtue. Tragedy, for me, is the life of skepticism, where the latter is the index for a certain moral orientation in the world, an orientation that seems to emerge from the disorientation of not knowing what to do. I hope to make good on this thought as we move through the following chapters.   In a lecture delivered in Oxford in 1908, Wilamowitz--Nietzsche's nemesis, who savaged some of the questionable philo­logical claims of The Birth of Tragedy --said,   The tradition yields us only ruins. The more closely we test and examine them, the more clearly we see how ruinous they are; and out of the ruins no whole can be built. The tradition is dead; our task is to revivify life that has passed away. We know that ghosts cannot speak until they have drunk blood; and the spirits which we evoke demand the blood of our hearts. We give it to them gladly.   Of course, the irony here is that Nietzsche says the same thing, namely that it is our blood that makes the ancients speak to us. Without wanting to piggyback on the dizzying recent success of vampire fiction, the latter's portion of truth is that the ancients need a little of our true blood in order to speak to us. When revived, we will notice that when the ancients speak, they do not merely tell us about themselves. They tell us about us. But who is that "us" that might still be claimed and compelled by these ancient texts, by these ruins? And here is both the beauty and strangeness of this thought: This "us" is not necessarily existent. It is us, but in some new way, some alien manner. It is us, but not as we have seen ourselves before, turned inside out and upside down.   Another way of putting this is to say that the "we" that we find in tragedy is invitational , an invitation to visit another sense of who we are and who we might become. I borrow this thought from Bernard Williams's Shame and Necessity, to which I will return in the following chapter. The idea of invitation has been interestingly developed by Raymond Geuss in the eponymous, final chapter of his A World without Why as a kind of procedure, if not a method. For Geuss, one is invited to look at two or more things placed in conjunction without necessarily asking the ques­tion why this is the case or seeking for a cause. A pile of dead bod­ies in a ditch in Iraq is placed alongside the prime minister of the United Kingdom speaking oleaginously in the House of Com­mons. Here, the idea of invitation can produce an unexpected juxtaposition or disjunction that provokes thinking. In my view, tragedy invites its audience to look at such disjunctions between two or more claims to truth, justice, or whatever without imme­diately seeking a unifying ground or reconciling the phenomena into a higher unity.   My concern in thinking about tragedy and what I will call "tragedy's philosophy" is to extend an invitation to you to become part of a "we," the "we" that is summoned and called into question by ancient tragedy. More simply stated, every generation has to reinvent the classics. I think it is the responsibility of every gen­eration to engage in this reinvention. And it is the very opposite of any and all kinds of cultural conservatism. If we don't accept this invitation, then we risk becoming even more stupefied by the present and endless onrush of the future. The nice thing is that stupefaction can be really easily avoided by nothing more difficult than reading, and most of the plays are not even that long, which is one reason why I like reading plays. Indeed, although this might sound pompous, I see this as the responsibility of each generation: to pass on something of the deep and unknown past in a way that will speak to the present and arrest us momentarily from the irre­sistible pull of the future. If the disavowal of the past through the endless production of the new is the very formula for ideology in our societies, then tragedy provides enduring resources for a critique of that ideology that might at least allow for the imagina­tion of a different range of human possibilities. First, however, we need to reach for the emergency brake: STOP! Excerpted from Tragedy, the Greeks and Us by Simon Critchley All rights reserved by the original copyright owners. Excerpts are provided for display purposes only and may not be reproduced, reprinted or distributed without the written permission of the publisher.