The dream of enlightenment The rise of modern philosophy

Anthony Gottlieb

Book - 2016

"Western philosophy is now two and a half millennia old, but much of it came in just two staccato bursts, each lasting only about 150 years. In his landmark survey of Western philosophy from the Greeks to the Renaissance, The Dream of Reason, Anthony Gottlieb documented the first burst, which came in the Athens of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. Now, in his sequel, The Dream of Enlightenment, Gottlieb expertly navigates a second great explosion of thought, taking us to northern Europe in the wake of its wars of religion and the rise of Galilean science. In a relatively short period--from the early 1640s to the eve of the French Revolution--Descartes, Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke, Leibniz, and Hume all made their mark. The Dream of Enlightenm...ent tells their story and that of the birth of modern philosophy. ..." -- dust jacket flap.

Saved in:

2nd Floor Show me where

190/Gottlieb
1 / 1 copies available
Location Call Number   Status
2nd Floor 190/Gottlieb Checked In
Subjects
Published
New York : Liveright Publishing Corporation, a division of W.W. Norton & Company [2016]
Language
English
Main Author
Anthony Gottlieb (author)
Edition
First edition
Physical Description
xi, 301 pages ; 25 cm
Bibliography
Includes bibliographical references (pages 245-281) and index.
ISBN
9780871404435
  • The Kingdome of darknesse
  • Chronological chart
  • Starting afresh : Descartes
  • The monster of Malmesbury : Hobbes
  • A breeze of the future : Spinoza
  • Philosophy for the British : Locke
  • An interlude on a comet : Bayle
  • The best of all possible compromises : Leibniz
  • A treatise of animal nature : Hume
  • What has the Enlightenment ever done for us? : Voltaire, Rousseau, and the Philosophes.
Review by Choice Review

Gottlieb's sequel to his much-lauded The Dream of Reason (CH, Jul'01, 38-6112), The Dream of Enlightenment is a well-researched, eminently readable survey of the Enlightenment era. Centering his discussion on themes of antidogmatism and progress, Gottlieb does a masterful job of describing the personal and intellectual lives of Descartes, Hobbes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Bayle, Locke, Hume, Voltaire, and Rousseau. In taking a biographical approach, Gottlieb humanizes otherwise abstract thought in a way rarely encountered in such surveys. He avoids ahistoricism: such occurrences as wars, excommunications, political scandals, natural disasters, and business ventures are deftly woven into the narrative. This book is not simply about philosophical ideas but also about the complex social factors that generated those ideas. The author subjects intellectual differences to close scrutiny, and his descriptions of the often-internecine feuds point to a far more complex "Age of Reason" than lay history would suggest. For the most part, Gottlieb skirts contemporary criticisms of the Enlightenment; his overall tone is decidedly triumphal. If there is any overarching fault with Gottlieb's book, it is that there is nothing really new about the story he tells. Thankfully, he tells it extremely well. Summing Up: Highly recommended. Lower- and upper-division undergraduates; general readers. --Lane Alan Wilkinson, University of Tennessee at Chattanooga

Copyright American Library Association, used with permission.
Review by New York Times Review

A MAN IS asleep at a table, his arms half-covering a drawing. Behind him a whole crowd of owls, bats, cats and less easily definable creatures hovers, crouches and flutters. One of the most humanoid of them is holding out a pen, and seems keen for the man to wake up. On the side of his table, written in large letters, are the words El sueño de la razón produce monstruos. We are looking at one of the etchings in Goya's late-18th-century work "Los Caprichos." The sleep of reason produces monsters. Or is it the dream of reason? The Spanish word allows either meaning. Goya's note on the etching suggests he inclined to the former sense: The monsters arrive when reason is no longer alert. But the other reading has a long and persuasive history: When reason dreams, it dreams of monsters. "The Dream of Reason," the first volume in a history of Western philosophy by Anthony Gottlieb, a former executive editor of The Economist, appeared in 2000, and took us from the ancient Greeks to the Renaissance. The new work starts with Descartes and ends on "the eve of the French Revolution." Another book is promised, picking up the tale with Kant. Gottlieb's aim, admirably fulfilled, is to help us see what older and newer philosophers have to say to us but not to turn them into mouthpieces for what we already think we know. "It is tempting to think that they speak our language and five in our world. But to understand them properly, we must step back into their shoes." This will be true no doubt of the post-Kantian volume as well. Even the shoes next door can look pretty strange if they belong to a philosopher. Philosophy is many things, Gottlieb suggests, including much that we no longer call philosophy, but one of its recurring features is what William James called "a peculiarly stubborn effort to think clearly." As Gottlieb declares in the first volume, the idea of clarity has not always seemed foremost, but the stubbornness is everywhere. "The attempt to push rational inquiry obstinately to its limits" is the name of the project. Sometimes it fails entirely, and the dream "seems merely a mirage." At other times, though, "it succeeds magnificently, and the dream is revealed as a fruitful inspiration." The dream appears as either fantasy or revelation, and Gottlieb skillfully tells "both sides of the story." But what about the monsters? Gottlieb reminds us that, for Bertrand Russell, Rousseau was responsible for the rise of Hitler, because his idea of a general will "made possible the mystic identification of a leader with his people." Leibniz was inclined "to confuse his own mind with that of God." Descartes "was too quick to assume that whatever seemed to him to be necessarily true was in fact so." Hobbes was "almost charmingly naïve" about the supposed rationality of sovereigns with absolute power. This last instance becomes especially strange when we think of Hobbes's eloquent elaborations of what people are like when left to their own devices ("no Knowledge of the face of the Earth; no account of Time ... no Society; and which is worst of all, continuall feare, and danger of violent death") but then, as Gottlieb shrewdly says, Hobbes "wanted above all to scare people by stressing the anarchy that would prevail in the absence of government." He could idealize government on the same pretext. Gottlieb is fully aware of the monsters in the dream, but doesn't allow them to dominate his book. He is committed to the positive aspects of inquiry, especially where scientific advances are involved. "It is by virtue of its engagement with the special problems posed by modern science that modern philosophy is distinguished from pre-modern philosophy." Gottlieb often makes fun of his philosophers, but gently, as a way of bringing us closer to them, and they emerge as brilliant, vulnerable humans rather than monsters of any kind. Descartes worried about "the divine insurance plan"; "Hobbes got rather carried away" when he told us how solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short life was. "If Leibniz had been a composer, most of his symphonies would have been unfinished." Descartes gets a slightly harder ride than the others, and Gottlieb seems to have changed his mind about him since he wrote the earlier book. There his writings were described as "engaging," and now they appear as "dubious" and "built on sand," with Descartes himself accused of "trying to work out too much in his head." This last remark looks like a rather odd verdict on a philosopher, but it makes sense in the context of the book, and of course Gottlieb is not denying Descartes's immense influence. All of Gottlieb's chief subjects - Descartes himself, Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke, Leibniz, Hume - are engaged, precisely and in a new way, with the world outside the head. Even geometry led to politics and social theory; advanced theoretical thought constantly engaged with the physical and mechanical sciences - for a long time these disciplines were still housed under the name of philosophy. There was plenty of room for work inside the head, of course, and as Gottlieb says, "philosophers always travel in several directions at once," but the material world was a laboratory and an authority replacing, even for religious thinkers, the old, unappealable orders of the church. Thus Hobbes sought to "disentangle politics and religion." Spinoza said, "I do not differentiate between God and Nature in the way all those known to me have done." Locke was suspicious of unempirical theories that "make the mind sound lazier than it is." And even Leibniz, whose interests ranged from waterworks and proto-computers to the secret order of the universe, insisted on the intimate relations of thought and substance, claiming "not only that matter cannot account for mind but that mind is needed to account for matter." Hume meanwhile taught that "extrapolating from experience" was just as unreliable as other philosophers thought it was but still more trustworthy than any other methods we might imagine we have. And Descartes, despite overdoing his mental homework, did not maintain, as he is often supposed to have done, that the mind and the body are irrevocably split from each other. "He could not explain how it is that mind and body are united, but he was sure that they were." The "Age of Reason" is a phrase usually applied to the 18th century, but Gottlieb invites us to take it all the way back to Descartes's "Discourse on Method" (1637) and his "Meditations" (1641), as long as we are willing to see reason as part of the puzzle rather than its solution. Is reason the same as enlightenment? For their conservative enemies, both are equally dangerous. Gottlieb's description of his 18th-century philosophers actually applies to all of those he discusses: "They were asking difficult questions where no questions should be asked." Did they spread light? Of course, but they didn't always know the answers to their questions, and this is why it is appropriate to think of enlightenment as a dream: It won't always translate into the working day. It's still a great achievement, of course, and Gottlieb gives the last quoted word to the French philosopher d'Alembert, who is defending knowledge against those who claim it is dangerous. He doesn't believe "that anything would be gained by destroying it. Vices would remain with us, and we would have ignorance in addition." To understand the 17th-century philosophers, we 'must step back into their shoes.' MICHAEL WOOD teaches at Princeton. His most recent book is "Alfred Hitchcock: The Man Who Knew Too Much."

Copyright (c) The New York Times Company [September 18, 2016]
Review by Publisher's Weekly Review

Gottlieb (The Dream of Reason), a former executive editor of the Economist, takes on the difficult task of trying to figure out what exactly the Enlightenment's greatest thinkers were thinking, and to describe their thoughts in lay terms. He draws on intellectual, political, and scientific developments in Europe from the 1630s to the French Revolution. Gottlieb begins with Descartes and progresses through Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke, Bayle, Leibniz, and Hume, concluding with Voltaire, Rousseau, and the Philosophes. Gottlieb skillfully juggles the biographical eccentricities of the philosophers and their enormous paper flow (some one million pages for Leibniz alone), but he takes on too much when he tries to show how these men, largely ill at ease with their peers and religious institutions, have been mishandled by such later thinkers as Kant and Pope John Paul II. The book overflows with information, but chapters could be better organized internally. Moreover, Gottlieb's writing can feel dull and uninspired given the material and his array of insights, including Locke's defense of serfdom and colonialism, and his possible theft of his theory on private property from a friend; Spinoza's influence on Einstein; and Hobbes's conviction that rational man would seek self-preservation and peace. The book has flaws, but Gottlieb's knowledge makes it worth reading. (Aug.) © Copyright PWxyz, LLC. All rights reserved.

(c) Copyright PWxyz, LLC. All rights reserved
Review by Library Journal Review

Gottlieb (former executive editor, the Economist) provides a sequel to The Dream of Reason: A History of Philosophy from the Greeks to the Renaissance. Here, there are individual chapters on René Descartes, Thomas Hobbes, Baruch Spinoza, John Locke, Pierre Bayle, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, David Hume, and other French philosophers. Gottlieb attempts to understand "these pioneers" by "step[ping] back into their shoes." He unpacks their major philosophical ideas from within the contexts of their lives and times and also traces their subsequent scholarly receptions. No small task, but one accomplished with delightfully economical prose. British philosophers get the most attention, with the longest chapters going to Hobbes, Locke, and Hume. And while Gottlieb acknowledges that "all histories of philosophy are selective," his might advantageously have included more on another Brit, Francis Bacon. That would have allowed highlighting inductive thinking to accompany Descartes's rationalism, even if Gottlieb is right that Bacon was not the stock empiricist he's often made out to be. We should all look forward to his projected next volume, taking philosophy's story forward from Immanuel Kant. VERDICT An accessible introduction to Enlightenment philosophers with much to offer all educated readers. [See Prepub Alert, 2/29/16.]-Mark Spencer, Brock Univ., St. Catharines, Ont. © Copyright 2016. Library Journals LLC, a wholly owned subsidiary of Media Source, Inc. No redistribution permitted.

(c) Copyright Library Journals LLC, a wholly owned subsidiary of Media Source, Inc. No redistribution permitted.